The obligation to obey the law the normative

Though 3 is logically independent of 1 and 21 seems to imply 2: The University of Chicago Press. These attitudes may be more prevalent, and more justifiable, than some philosophers suppose.

Most importantly, however, Hart argues Austin overlooks the existence of secondary meta-rules that have as their subject matter the primary rules themselves and distinguish full-blown legal systems from primitive systems of law: As Hart describes it, the Separability Thesis is no more than the "simple contention that it is in no sense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain demands of morality, though in fact they have often done so" Hartpp.

Additionally, critical race theorists show how the experience, concerns, values, and perspectives of persons of color are systematically excluded from mainstream discourse among practicing lawyers, judges, and legislators.

The Practice of Principle.

Normative Jurisprudence

These focus on the questions of whether it is in fact given and, if given, whether it would bind. The core idea is that those who accept the benefits of fair scheme of cooperation have a duty to do their allotted part under that scheme: Some contemporary writers take a related view.

Even if valid law is bad law, we have some obligation to obey it simply because it is law. But if law is radically indeterminate, then judges nearly always decide cases by making new law, which is inconsistent with liberal conceptions of the legitimate sources of lawmaking authority.

The extent to which people need authoritative guidance to secure cooperation varies with context. Hart takes a different view of the Social Fact Thesis. The legal economists, led by Richard Posner, argue that the content of many areas of the common law can be explained in terms of its tendency to maximize preferences: Indeed, the realist acknowledges that law is essentially the product of official activity, but believes that judicial lawmaking occurs more frequently than is commonly assumed.

Philosophy of Law

Positivism defends a particular conception, and I have tried to defend a competing conception. On the Kantian side, the law should facilitate market transactions because market transactions best reflect autonomous judgments about the value of individual preferences. Having a virgin birth, obligation has no father among familiar moral principles such as consent, utility, fairness, and so on.

Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics.

Legal Obligation and Authority

We need to ensure that consent is not defeated by mistake, coercion or duress. Gerald Dworkin"Paternalism," The Monist, vol.

The Ethics of Deference: Thomas Aquinas and William Blackstone.

The Obligation to Obey the Law

That suggests that NJT covers only a narrow range of legitimate state activity. Nevertheless, since judges are bound to consider such principles when relevant, they must be characterized as law.

We cannot ask which or what sort of authority is justified over both the Kurds and the Shiites in Iraq until we answer why there should be one at all.

Posner subscribes to the so-called efficiency theory of the common law, according to which "the common law is best not perfectly explained as a system for maximizing the wealth of society" Posnerp.

Moral Principles and Political Obligations. This is bound to be a somewhat loose fit—the institutional and bureaucratic structure of law means that it will generally be an imperfect expression of the society it regulates. While this task is usually interpreted as an attempt to analyze the concepts of law and legal system, there is some confusion as to both the value and character of conceptual analysis in philosophy of law.

And law can solve some problems of cooperation simply providing information or by restructuring incentives see Green89— Contemporary positivists, for the most part, accept the idea that positivism is inconsistent with an obligation to obey law qua law compare Himmabut argue that the mere status of a norm as law cannot give rise to any moral obligation to obey that norm.

TenCrime, Guilt, and Punishment Oxford: Little, Brown, and Company. As Hart points out, the rules governing the creation of contracts and wills cannot plausibly be characterized as restrictions on freedom that are backed by the threat of a sanction.

Too Many Requests

This is not an impossibility proof—only anarchists like Wolff think that justified political authority is impossible. A flourishing friendship does, however, bring obligations in train. Scepticism and anarchism As the above survey suggests, there are plausible objections to each of the dominant justifications for the duty to obey the law.

Borrowing heavily from Jeremy BenthamJohn Austin argues that the principal distinguishing feature of a legal system is the presence of a sovereign who is habitually obeyed by most people in the society, but not in the habit of obeying any determinate human superior.

It is uncertain how far deference to authority is really needed here. In essence, this is a voluntarist version of the theory of constitutive obligations considered above in Section 4. In a market transaction with no third-party effects, wealth is increased because all parties are made better off by the transaction-otherwise there would be no incentive to consummate the transaction-and no one is made worse off.

A legal practice can be understood from the "internal" point of view of the person who accepts that practice as providing legitimate guides to conduct, as well as from the "external" point of view of the observer who wishes to understand the practice but does not accept it as being authoritative or legitimate.

For helpful assessments of other theories, see also Wasserstrom ; Smith ; and Simmons Natural law critics of positivism (for example, Fuller ) frequently complain that if positivism is correct, there cannot be a moral obligation to obey the law qua law (that is, to obey the law as such, no matter what the laws are, simply because it is the law).

The obligation to obey the law - the normative phenomenon in jurisprudence. Introduction: This dissertation aims to provide a general discourse into the normative jurisprudential phenomenon of. The first section of the chapter discusses the nature of the claim that one has an obligation to obey the law.

The chapter also examines the case for the existence of such obligation arising from moral and prudential considerations.

The question whether there is an obligation of obedience to law is a matter of whether we should act from the legal point of view and obey the law as it claims to be obeyed (Raz–49). It is an interesting feature of this account that it supposes that one can tell what the authority requires independent of whether the requirement is.

LAWAND OBLIGATION STEPHEN PERRY* 1. INTRODUCTION it cannot have normative content other than the general moral obligation to obey the law, on the other. II. AUTHORlTY, OBLIGATION, AND LIABILITY There is undeniably at least a kernel oftruth to the view that possessing.

it is almost certainly true that there is a legal obligation to obey the law, however, and because Raz himself says that "It]he obligation to obey the law is generally thought of as a moral obligation," id.

athis claim apparently is about moral obligation.

Download
The obligation to obey the law the normative
Rated 4/5 based on 11 review